subject | book bibliographic info |
---|---|
dialectic/metaphysics, hypothesis in | d'Hoine and Martijn, All From One: A Guide to Proclus (2017) 178 |
metaphysic, of mind | Osborne, Irenaeus of Lyons (2001) 32, 33, 34, 35, 36, 37, 38, 165, 166, 167, 177 |
metaphysical | Garcia, On Human Nature in Early Judaism: Creation, Composition, and Condition (2021) 24, 64, 77, 82, 107, 108, 112, 115, 122, 125, 127, 128, 133, 137, 145, 146, 150, 152, 162, 165, 183, 194, 205, 270 Černušková, Kovacs and Plátová, Clement’s Biblical Exegesis: Proceedings of the Second Colloquium on Clement of Alexandria (2016) 19, 153, 159, 273, 277, 285, 288 |
metaphysical, and curse, pollution | Petrovic and Petrovic, Inner Purity and Pollution in Greek Religion (2016) 215 |
metaphysical, and erotic madness, pollution | Petrovic and Petrovic, Inner Purity and Pollution in Greek Religion (2016) 215 |
metaphysical, and killing, pollution | Petrovic and Petrovic, Inner Purity and Pollution in Greek Religion (2016) 133, 147 |
metaphysical, and oath-breaking, pollution | Petrovic and Petrovic, Inner Purity and Pollution in Greek Religion (2016) 86, 122, 123, 278 |
metaphysical, and political regimes of bureaucratic modes of knowing | Ayres Champion and Crawford, The Intellectual World of Late Antique Christianity: Reshaping Classical Traditions (2023) 593, 594, 595 |
metaphysical, assumptions, propositional trust, as defence of | Morgan, The New Testament and the Theology of Trust: 'This Rich Trust' (2022) 353 |
metaphysical, background of ethics | d'Hoine and Martijn, All From One: A Guide to Proclus (2017) 270, 271, 272, 273 |
metaphysical, conversion conversion, epistrophe | Tanaseanu-Döbler and von Alvensleben, Athens II: Athens in Late Antiquity (2020) 337, 346 |
metaphysical, disposition category | Ebrey and Kraut, The Cambridge Companion to Plato, 2nd ed (2022) 191, 337, 531, 547 |
metaphysical, doctrines | Petersen and van Kooten, Religio-Philosophical Discourses in the Mediterranean World: From Plato, through Jesus, to Late Antiquity (2017) 326 |
metaphysical, interpretation of parmenides, iamblichus | d'Hoine and Martijn, All From One: A Guide to Proclus (2017) 208 |
metaphysical, multiplicity | Tanaseanu-Döbler and von Alvensleben, Athens II: Athens in Late Antiquity (2020) 16, 304, 308, 326, 327, 328, 329, 335, 338, 339, 340, 356, 362, 364 |
metaphysical, one | Tanaseanu-Döbler and von Alvensleben, Athens II: Athens in Late Antiquity (2020) 16, 28, 243, 301, 302, 303, 304, 305, 306, 307, 308, 309, 310, 320, 330, 341, 356, 361 |
metaphysical, one-being, one | Tanaseanu-Döbler and von Alvensleben, Athens II: Athens in Late Antiquity (2020) 16, 301, 304, 305, 306, 307, 310, 361 |
metaphysical, philosophy | MacDougall, Philosophy at the Festival: The Festal Orations of Gregory of Nazianzus and the Classical Tradition (2022) 2 |
metaphysical, philosophy/philosophers | Černušková, Kovacs and Plátová, Clement’s Biblical Exegesis: Proceedings of the Second Colloquium on Clement of Alexandria (2016) 159 |
metaphysical, pollution | Petrovic and Petrovic, Inner Purity and Pollution in Greek Religion (2016) 21, 23, 29, 30, 31, 32, 34, 51, 62, 167, 169, 182, 233, 234, 239, 260, 282, 283, 290 |
metaphysical, pollution, agos, as | Petrovic and Petrovic, Inner Purity and Pollution in Greek Religion (2016) 30, 31, 32, 33, 34 |
metaphysical, principle, all-one as a | Schultz and Wilberding, Women and the Female in Neoplatonism (2022) 129, 130, 131, 132, 133, 134, 135 |
metaphysical, principle, difference as a | Schultz and Wilberding, Women and the Female in Neoplatonism (2022) 85, 111, 112, 113, 240, 249 |
metaphysical, principle, life as | Schultz and Wilberding, Women and the Female in Neoplatonism (2022) 132, 133, 159, 224, 225, 228, 232, 234, 235, 236, 239, 240, 246 |
metaphysical, principle, meadow as | Schultz and Wilberding, Women and the Female in Neoplatonism (2022) 228, 231, 234, 235, 238, 239, 240, 241, 246, 247 |
metaphysical, principle, power as | Schultz and Wilberding, Women and the Female in Neoplatonism (2022) 48, 51, 54, 81, 83, 105, 106, 108, 115, 116, 120, 129, 131, 132, 133, 134, 136, 137, 173, 174, 177, 180, 181, 182, 183, 184, 185, 187, 190, 191, 200, 205, 209, 211, 212, 213, 223, 224, 225, 227, 229, 232, 233, 234, 235, 237, 238, 239, 240, 241, 242, 243, 246, 248, 249, 260, 264 |
metaphysical, principle, subordination, and inferiority, of the female as a | Schultz and Wilberding, Women and the Female in Neoplatonism (2022) 59, 60, 104, 108, 111, 115, 134, 136, 139, 140, 148, 149, 158, 161, 162, 166, 184, 185, 223, 234, 265 |
metaphysical, procession proodos | Tanaseanu-Döbler and von Alvensleben, Athens II: Athens in Late Antiquity (2020) 304, 308, 327, 330, 336, 342, 374 |
metaphysical, skepticism | Tarrant et al, Brill's Companion to the Reception of Plato in Antiquity (2018) 136, 138 |
metaphysical, system, σύστηµα/συστήµατα, of philosophy, of doctrine / | Motta and Petrucci, Isagogical Crossroads from the Early Imperial Age to the End of Antiquity (2022) 4, 14, 15, 21, 34, 48, 68, 92, 94, 95, 96, 97, 99, 100, 102, 103, 104, 105, 108, 109, 110, 118 |
metaphysical, unity, unity | Tanaseanu-Döbler and von Alvensleben, Athens II: Athens in Late Antiquity (2020) 16, 33, 34, 310, 323, 326, 328, 329, 330, 331, 332, 333, 334, 335, 344, 346, 356, 360, 362 |
metaphysical, vulnerability | Legaspi, Wisdom in Classical and Biblical Tradition (2018) 63, 64, 79, 80, 81, 106, 107, 251 |
metaphysical, works, aristotle, metaphysics | Singer and van Eijk, Galen: Works on Human Nature: Volume 1, Mixtures (De Temperamentis) (2018) 78, 80, 123 |
metaphysically, inclined skepticism, skepticism | Vogt, Pyrrhonian Skepticism in Diogenes Laertius (2015) 11 |
metaphysics | Corrigan and Rasimus, Gnosticism, Platonism and the Late Ancient World (2013) 8, 82, 203, 299, 301, 326, 382, 386, 420, 427, 428, 437, 468, 472, 482, 502, 504, 506, 527, 534, 537, 544, 545, 547, 549, 551, 553, 555, 556, 558, 581, 582 Edelmann-Singer et al., Sceptic and Believer in Ancient Mediterranean Religions (2020) 7, 45, 50, 89, 131, 241 Erler et al., Authority and Authoritative Texts in the Platonist Tradition (2021) 17, 18, 32, 33, 34, 144, 173, 175, 203, 205, 209, 213, 214, 223, 243, 244 Fialová Hoblík and Kitzler, Hellenism, Early Judaism, and Early Christianity: Transmission and Transformation of Ideas (2022) 69, 77, 98, 100 Horkey, Cosmos in the Ancient World (2019) 20, 33, 62, 66, 96, 112, 286, 295 Long, From Epicurus to Epictetus Studies in Hellenistic and Roman Philosophy (2006) 239, 240, 251, 264, 274, 275, 364 Malherbe et al., Light from the Gentiles: Hellenistic Philosophy and Early Christianity: Collected Essays of Abraham J (2014) 818, 819, 876 Motta and Petrucci, Isagogical Crossroads from the Early Imperial Age to the End of Antiquity (2022) 7, 17, 35, 79, 83, 105, 106, 107, 117, 185 Novenson, Monotheism and Christology in Greco-Roman Antiquity (2020) 27, 38, 60, 144, 145, 146, 165, 251, 252, 258, 259, 260, 261, 275, 282, 297 Petersen and van Kooten, Religio-Philosophical Discourses in the Mediterranean World: From Plato, through Jesus, to Late Antiquity (2017) 56, 85 Rohmann, Christianity, Book-Burning and Censorship in Late Antiquity (2016) 159 Seaford, Wilkins, Wright, Selfhood and the Soul: Essays on Ancient Thought and Literature in Honour of Christopher Gill (2017) 6, 37, 40, 41, 42, 46, 73, 76, 81, 85, 131, 205, 264 Singer and van Eijk, Galen: Works on Human Nature: Volume 1, Mixtures (De Temperamentis) (2018) 155 n. 6 d'Hoine and Martijn, All From One: A Guide to Proclus (2017) 31, 108, 184 |
metaphysics, /, metaphysical, | Lee, Moral Transformation in Greco-Roman Philosophy of Mind: Mapping the Moral Milieu of the Apostle Paul and His Diaspora Jewish Contemporaries (2020) 7, 55, 56, 106, 107, 111, 121, 122, 129, 130, 132, 133, 135, 136, 137, 140, 143, 144, 148, 149, 150, 157, 321, 322, 502, 534 |
metaphysics, a, aristotelianism | Osborne, Eros Unveiled: Plato and the God of Love (1996) 137 |
metaphysics, apuleius’s treatment of | Hoenig, Plato's Timaeus and the Latin Tradition (2018) 144 |
metaphysics, aristotle | Celykte, The Stoic Theory of Beauty (2020) 178 Erler et al., Authority and Authoritative Texts in the Platonist Tradition (2021) 163, 164, 166, 175 Gerson and Wilberding, The New Cambridge Companion to Plotinus (2022) 16, 36, 100, 120, 181, 194, 208, 272, 310 Harte, Rereading Ancient Philosophy: Old Chestnuts and Sacred Cows (2017) 29, 185 Joosse, Olympiodorus of Alexandria: Exegete, Teacher, Platonic Philosopher (2021) 34 Neusner Green and Avery-Peck, Judaism from Moses to Muhammad: An Interpretation: Turning Points and Focal Points (2022) 48 Star, Apocalypse and Golden Age: The End of the World in Greek and Roman Thought (2021) 40 Tsouni, Antiochus and Peripatetic Ethics (2019) 142, 147 Walter, Time in Ancient Stories of Origin (2020) 11 Zachhuber, Time and Soul: From Aristotle to St. Augustine (2022) 19, 23, 24, 25, 42, 43, 48 |
metaphysics, commentary on aristotles | d'Hoine and Martijn, All From One: A Guide to Proclus (2017) 29, 169, 170, 172, 195 |
metaphysics, creation | Yates and Dupont, The Bible in Christian North Africa: Part II: Consolidation of the Canon to the Arab Conquest (ca. 393 to 650 CE). (2023) 107, 108, 109, 110, 111, 112 |
metaphysics, demiurge, in plotinus' | Marmodoro and Prince, Causation and Creation in Late Antiquity (2015) 53 |
metaphysics, dualism, of plato’s | Hoenig, Plato's Timaeus and the Latin Tradition (2018) 251 |
metaphysics, epistemology in relation to | d'Hoine and Martijn, All From One: A Guide to Proclus (2017) 28, 60 |
metaphysics, in calcidius’s commentary | Hoenig, Plato's Timaeus and the Latin Tradition (2018) 208 |
metaphysics, in platonic curriculum | Hoenig, Plato's Timaeus and the Latin Tradition (2018) 107 |
metaphysics, influence on augustine | Hoenig, Plato's Timaeus and the Latin Tradition (2018) 249, 250, 251, 252, 253, 254, 255, 256, 257, 258, 259, 260, 261, 262, 263, 264, 265, 266, 267, 268, 269, 270 |
metaphysics, nature | Rüpke and Woolf, Religious Dimensions of the Self in the Second Century CE (2013) 4, 6, 8, 13, 78, 97 |
metaphysics, neo-platonic | Petersen and van Kooten, Religio-Philosophical Discourses in the Mediterranean World: From Plato, through Jesus, to Late Antiquity (2017) 338 |
metaphysics, new musicians, aristotle | Cosgrove, Music at Social Meals in Greek and Roman Antiquity: From the Archaic Period to the Age of Augustine (2022) 88 |
metaphysics, of forms | Petersen and van Kooten, Religio-Philosophical Discourses in the Mediterranean World: From Plato, through Jesus, to Late Antiquity (2017) 56 |
metaphysics, of identity | Seaford, Wilkins, Wright, Selfhood and the Soul: Essays on Ancient Thought and Literature in Honour of Christopher Gill (2017) 78, 81, 83, 85, 86 |
metaphysics, of plotinus | Ayres Champion and Crawford, The Intellectual World of Late Antique Christianity: Reshaping Classical Traditions (2023) 143 |
metaphysics, of tyranny | Munn, The Mother of the Gods, Athens, and the Tyranny of Asia: A Study of Sovereignty in Ancient Religion (2006) 36, 37, 92, 93, 97, 98, 99, 100, 101, 102, 130, 153, 154, 155, 179, 184, 188, 189, 190, 193, 196, 197, 202, 203, 204, 205, 206, 207, 208, 218, 221, 222, 224, 225 |
metaphysics, plato’s, in timaeus | Hoenig, Plato's Timaeus and the Latin Tradition (2018) 251 |
metaphysics, plotinian | Hoenig, Plato's Timaeus and the Latin Tradition (2018) 24 |
metaphysics, prepositional | Novenson, Monotheism and Christology in Greco-Roman Antiquity (2020) 27, 144, 145, 146, 165, 169 |
metaphysics, proclus diadochus, survey of proclus’ | Ayres Champion and Crawford, The Intellectual World of Late Antique Christianity: Reshaping Classical Traditions (2023) 595, 596, 597, 598 |
metaphysics, sight and, melchizedek | Birnbaum and Dillon, Philo of Alexandria: On the Life of Abraham: Introduction, Translation, and Commentary (2020) 299 |
metaphysics, simplified | Joosse, Olympiodorus of Alexandria: Exegete, Teacher, Platonic Philosopher (2021) 2, 212, 217 |
metaphysics, theophrastus | Tsouni, Antiochus and Peripatetic Ethics (2019) 194 |
metaphysics, trinitarian | Hoenig, Plato's Timaeus and the Latin Tradition (2018) 252, 258, 279 |
metaphysics, unmoved mover in | Marmodoro and Prince, Causation and Creation in Late Antiquity (2015) 132 |
metaphysics, xii, themistius, paraphrase of aristotle’s | Zachhuber, Time and Soul: From Aristotle to St. Augustine (2022) 42, 43 |
metaphysics/-al, and aesthetics | d'Hoine and Martijn, All From One: A Guide to Proclus (2017) 277, 280, 282, 285, 286 |
metaphysics/-al, and mathematics | d'Hoine and Martijn, All From One: A Guide to Proclus (2017) 168, 169, 173, 174, 178, 179 |
metaphysics/-al, in relation to theology | d'Hoine and Martijn, All From One: A Guide to Proclus (2017) 213 |
metaphysics/-al, reading of the parmenides | d'Hoine and Martijn, All From One: A Guide to Proclus (2017) 112 |
metaphysics/-al, relevance to politics | d'Hoine and Martijn, All From One: A Guide to Proclus (2017) 273 |
metaphysics/-al, unhypothetical | d'Hoine and Martijn, All From One: A Guide to Proclus (2017) 178 |
spiritual/metaphysical, self-motion | d'Hoine and Martijn, All From One: A Guide to Proclus (2017) 54, 55, 58, 63, 69, 126 |
32 validated results for "metaphysical" |
---|
1. Hebrew Bible, Genesis, 1.1-1.3, 1.26, 2.7, 2.20 (9th cent. BCE - 3rd cent. BCE) Tagged with subjects: • Metaphysics • creation, metaphysics • metaphysical • metaphysical vulnerability • metaphysics • prepositional metaphysics Found in books: Corrigan and Rasimus, Gnosticism, Platonism and the Late Ancient World (2013) 8; Garcia, On Human Nature in Early Judaism: Creation, Composition, and Condition (2021) 64, 150; Horkey, Cosmos in the Ancient World (2019) 20; Legaspi, Wisdom in Classical and Biblical Tradition (2018) 106; Novenson, Monotheism and Christology in Greco-Roman Antiquity (2020) 145, 165; Yates and Dupont, The Bible in Christian North Africa: Part II: Consolidation of the Canon to the Arab Conquest (ca. 393 to 650 CE). (2023) 109, 111 1.1 וַיִּקְרָא אֱלֹהִים לַיַּבָּשָׁה אֶרֶץ וּלְמִקְוֵה הַמַּיִם קָרָא יַמִּים וַיַּרְא אֱלֹהִים כִּי־טוֹב׃, 1.2 וַיֹּאמֶר אֱלֹהִים יִשְׁרְצוּ הַמַּיִם שֶׁרֶץ נֶפֶשׁ חַיָּה וְעוֹף יְעוֹפֵף עַל־הָאָרֶץ עַל־פְּנֵי רְקִיעַ הַשָּׁמָיִם׃, 1.3 וּלְכָל־חַיַּת הָאָרֶץ וּלְכָל־עוֹף הַשָּׁמַיִם וּלְכֹל רוֹמֵשׂ עַל־הָאָרֶץ אֲשֶׁר־בּוֹ נֶפֶשׁ חַיָּה אֶת־כָּל־יֶרֶק עֵשֶׂב לְאָכְלָה וַיְהִי־כֵן׃, 1.26 וַיֹּאמֶר אֱלֹהִים נַעֲשֶׂה אָדָם בְּצַלְמֵנוּ כִּדְמוּתֵנוּ וְיִרְדּוּ בִדְגַת הַיָּם וּבְעוֹף הַשָּׁמַיִם וּבַבְּהֵמָה וּבְכָל־הָאָרֶץ וּבְכָל־הָרֶמֶשׂ הָרֹמֵשׂ עַל־הָאָרֶץ׃, 2.7 וַיִּיצֶר יְהוָה אֱלֹהִים אֶת־הָאָדָם עָפָר מִן־הָאֲדָמָה וַיִּפַּח בְּאַפָּיו נִשְׁמַת חַיִּים וַיְהִי הָאָדָם לְנֶפֶשׁ חַיָּה׃, 1.1 In the beginning God created the heaven and the earth. 1.2 Now the earth was unformed and void, and darkness was upon the face of the deep; and the spirit of God hovered over the face of the waters. 1.3 And God said: ‘Let there be light.’ And there was light. 1.26 And God said: ‘Let us make man in our image, after our likeness; and let them have dominion over the fish of the sea, and over the fowl of the air, and over the cattle, and over all the earth, and over every creeping thing that creepeth upon the earth.’, 2.7 Then the LORD God formed man of the dust of the ground, and breathed into his nostrils the breath of life; and man became a living soul. 2.20 And the man gave names to all cattle, and to the fowl of the air, and to every beast of the field; but for Adam there was not found a help meet for him. |
2. Aeschylus, Eumenides, 166 (6th cent. BCE - 5th cent. BCE) Tagged with subjects: • pollution, metaphysical, and killing • tyranny, metaphysics of Found in books: Munn, The Mother of the Gods, Athens, and the Tyranny of Asia: A Study of Sovereignty in Ancient Religion (2006) 193; Petrovic and Petrovic, Inner Purity and Pollution in Greek Religion (2016) 147 πάρεστι γᾶς ὀμφαλὸν προσδρακεῖν αἱμάτων NA> |
3. Theognis, Elegies, 89, 197-208, 225-226 (6th cent. BCE - 5th cent. BCE) Tagged with subjects: • Aristotle, Metaphysics, • pollution, metaphysical • pollution, metaphysical, and oath-breaking Found in books: Bowie, Essays on Ancient Greek Literature and Culture (2021) 271; Petrovic and Petrovic, Inner Purity and Pollution in Greek Religion (2016) 122, 123, 283 " 197 A possession that cometh from Zeus, and of right and in seemly wise, abideth evermore; but if one shall win it unrighteously and unduly with a covetous heart, or by unrighteous seizure upon an oath, at the first him seemeth to get him gain, but in the end it becometh bad likewise, and the mind of the Gods overcometh him. But these things deceive mans understanding, seeing that the Blessed Ones requite not wrongdoing at the moment; nay, albeit this man may pay his evil debt himself and not make ruin to overhang his dear children after him, that other man Retribution overtaketh not, because too soon did unconscionable Death settle upon his eyelids fraught with his Doom.", |
4. Plato, Parmenides, 138a (5th cent. BCE - 4th cent. BCE) Tagged with subjects: • Metaphysics • One (metaphysical) • One (metaphysical), One-Being Found in books: Corrigan and Rasimus, Gnosticism, Platonism and the Late Ancient World (2013) 558; Tanaseanu-Döbler and von Alvensleben, Athens II: Athens in Late Antiquity (2020) 306, 307 138a περιφερές ἐστιν, ἐπείπερ οὐδὲ μέρη ἔχει. ὀρθῶς. 138a “Right.” “Moreover, being of such a nature, it cannot be anywhere, for it could not be either in anything else or in itself.” “How is that?” “If it were in something else, it would be encircled by that in which it would be and would be touched in many places by many parts of it; but that which is one and without parts and does not partake of the circular nature cannot be touched by a circle in many places.” “No, it cannot.” “But, furthermore, being in itself it would also be surrounding with itself naught other than itself, 138b if it were in itself; for nothing can be in anything which does not surround it.” “No, it cannot.” “Then that which surrounds would be other than that which is surrounded; for a whole cannot be both active and passive in the same action; and thus one would be no longer one, but two.” “True.” “Then the one is not anywhere, neither in itself nor in something else.” “No, it is not.” “This being the case, see whether it can be either at rest or in motion.” “Why not?” |
5. Plato, Phaedrus, 245c, 247c, 250b, 250c, 264c (5th cent. BCE - 4th cent. BCE) Tagged with subjects: • Metaphysics • One (metaphysical) • One (metaphysical), One-Being • Principles (in the metaphysical sense) • System (σύστηµα/συστήµατα), of Philosophy, of doctrine / metaphysical • metaphysics • metaphysics / metaphysical • metaphysics, Plotinian • metaphysics/-al and aesthetics Found in books: Corrigan and Rasimus, Gnosticism, Platonism and the Late Ancient World (2013) 549; Delcomminette, d’Hoine, and Gavray, Ancient Readings of Plato’s Phaedo (2015) 165, 166; Erler et al., Authority and Authoritative Texts in the Platonist Tradition (2021) 214; Hoenig, Plato's Timaeus and the Latin Tradition (2018) 24; Lee, Moral Transformation in Greco-Roman Philosophy of Mind: Mapping the Moral Milieu of the Apostle Paul and His Diaspora Jewish Contemporaries (2020) 107; Motta and Petrucci, Isagogical Crossroads from the Early Imperial Age to the End of Antiquity (2022) 4; Tanaseanu-Döbler and von Alvensleben, Athens II: Athens in Late Antiquity (2020) 305; d'Hoine and Martijn, All From One: A Guide to Proclus (2017) 285 245c παρὰ θεῶν ἡ τοιαύτη μανία δίδοται· ἡ δὲ δὴ ἀπόδειξις ἔσται δεινοῖς μὲν ἄπιστος, σοφοῖς δὲ πιστή. δεῖ οὖν πρῶτον ψυχῆς φύσεως πέρι θείας τε καὶ ἀνθρωπίνης ἰδόντα πάθη τε καὶ ἔργα τἀληθὲς νοῆσαι· ἀρχὴ δὲ ἀποδείξεως ἥδε. 247c νώτῳ, στάσας δὲ αὐτὰς περιάγει ἡ περιφορά, αἱ δὲ θεωροῦσι τὰ ἔξω τοῦ οὐρανοῦ. 250b διὰ τὸ μὴ ἱκανῶς διαισθάνεσθαι. δικαιοσύνης μὲν οὖν καὶ σωφροσύνης καὶ ὅσα ἄλλα τίμια ψυχαῖς οὐκ ἔνεστι φέγγος οὐδὲν ἐν τοῖς τῇδε ὁμοιώμασιν, ἀλλὰ διʼ ἀμυδρῶν ὀργάνων μόγις αὐτῶν καὶ ὀλίγοι ἐπὶ τὰς εἰκόνας ἰόντες θεῶνται τὸ τοῦ εἰκασθέντος γένος· κάλλος δὲ τότʼ ἦν ἰδεῖν λαμπρόν, ὅτε σὺν εὐδαίμονι χορῷ μακαρίαν ὄψιν τε καὶ θέαν, ἑπόμενοι μετὰ μὲν Διὸς ἡμεῖς, ἄλλοι δὲ μετʼ ἄλλου θεῶν, εἶδόν τε καὶ ἐτελοῦντο τῶν τελετῶν ἣν θέμις λέγειν, 250c μακαριωτάτην, ἣν ὠργιάζομεν ὁλόκληροι μὲν αὐτοὶ ὄντες καὶ ἀπαθεῖς κακῶν ὅσα ἡμᾶς ἐν ὑστέρῳ χρόνῳ ὑπέμενεν, ὁλόκληρα δὲ καὶ ἁπλᾶ καὶ ἀτρεμῆ καὶ εὐδαίμονα φάσματα μυούμενοί τε καὶ ἐποπτεύοντες ἐν αὐγῇ καθαρᾷ, καθαροὶ ὄντες καὶ ἀσήμαντοι τούτου ὃ νῦν δὴ σῶμα περιφέροντες ὀνομάζομεν, ὀστρέου τρόπον δεδεσμευμένοι. 264c οὕτως ἀκριβῶς διιδεῖν. ΣΩ. ἀλλὰ τόδε γε οἶμαί σε φάναι ἄν, δεῖν πάντα λόγον ὥσπερ ζῷον συνεστάναι σῶμά τι ἔχοντα αὐτὸν αὑτοῦ, ὥστε μήτε ἀκέφαλον εἶναι μήτε ἄπουν, ἀλλὰ μέσα τε ἔχειν καὶ ἄκρα, πρέποντα ἀλλήλοις καὶ τῷ ὅλῳ γεγραμμένα. ΦΑΙ. πῶς γὰρ οὔ; ΣΩ. σκέψαι τοίνυν τὸν τοῦ ἑταίρου σου λόγον εἴτε οὕτως εἴτε ἄλλως ἔχει, καὶ εὑρήσεις τοῦ ἐπιγράμματος οὐδὲν διαφέροντα, ὃ Μίδᾳ τῷ Φρυγί φασίν τινες ἐπιγεγράφθαι. 245c is given by the gods for our greatest happiness; and our proof will not be believed by the merely clever, but will be accepted by the truly wise. First, then, we must learn the truth about the soul divine and human by observing how it acts and is acted upon. And the beginning of our proof is as follows: Every soul is immortal. For that which is ever moving is immortal but that which moves something else or is moved by something else, when it ceases to move, ceases to live. Only that which moves itself, since it does not leave itself, never ceases to move, and this is also 247c pass outside and take their place on the outer surface of the heaven, and when they have taken their stand, the revolution carries them round and they behold the things outside of the heaven. But the region above the heaven was never worthily sung by any earthly poet, nor will it ever be. It is, however, as I shall tell; for I must dare to speak the truth, especially as truth is my theme. For the colorless, formless, and intangible truly existing essence, with which all true knowledge is concerned, holds this region, 250b Now in the earthly copies of justice and temperance and the other ideas which are precious to souls there is no light, but only a few, approaching the images through the darkling organs of sense, behold in them the nature of that which they imitate, and these few do this with difficulty. But at that former time they saw beauty shining in brightness, when, with a blessed company—we following in the train of Zeus, and others in that of some other god—they saw the blessed sight and vision and were initiated into that which is rightly called, 250c the most blessed of mysteries, which we celebrated in a state of perfection, when we were without experience of the evils which awaited us in the time to come, being permitted as initiates to the sight of perfect and simple and calm and happy apparitions, which we saw in the pure light, being ourselves pure and not entombed in this which we carry about with us and call the body, in which we are imprisoned like an oyster in its shell. So much, then, in honor of memory, on account of which I have now spoken at some length, through yearning for the joys of that other time. But beauty, 264c Phaedrus. You flatter me in thinking that I can discern his motives so accurately. Socrates. But I do think you will agree to this, that every discourse must be organized, like a living being, with a body of its own, as it were, so as not to be headless or footless, but to have a middle and members, composed in fitting relation to each other and to the whole. Phaedrus. Certainly. Socrates. See then whether this is the case with your friend’s discourse, or not. You will find, |
6. Plato, Republic, 6, 6.500c, 7, 509d (5th cent. BCE - 4th cent. BCE) Tagged with subjects: • Metaphysics • Plotinus, metaphysics of • metaphysics • metaphysics / metaphysical • metaphysics/-al and mathematics • theology, metaphysics Found in books: Ayres Champion and Crawford, The Intellectual World of Late Antique Christianity: Reshaping Classical Traditions (2023) 143; Corrigan and Rasimus, Gnosticism, Platonism and the Late Ancient World (2013) 582; Erler et al., Authority and Authoritative Texts in the Platonist Tradition (2021) 32; Fowler, Plato in the Third Sophistic (2014) 134; Lee, Moral Transformation in Greco-Roman Philosophy of Mind: Mapping the Moral Milieu of the Apostle Paul and His Diaspora Jewish Contemporaries (2020) 137; Novenson, Monotheism and Christology in Greco-Roman Antiquity (2020) 251; d'Hoine and Martijn, All From One: A Guide to Proclus (2017) 168 509d he said. “Conceive then,” said I, “as we were saying, that there are these two entities, and that one of them is sovereign over the intelligible order and region and the other over the world of the eye-ball, not to say the sky-ball, but let that pass. You surely apprehend the two types, the visible and the intelligible.”“I do.”“Represent them then, as it were, by a line divided into two unequal sections and cut each section again in the same ratio (the section, that is, of the visible and that of the intelligible order), and then as an expression of the ratio of their comparative clearness and obscurity you will have, as one of the sections of the visible world, images. By images I mean, |
7. Plato, Symposium, 203b (5th cent. BCE - 4th cent. BCE) Tagged with subjects: • Power as Metaphysical Principle • metaphysical background of ethics Found in books: Schultz and Wilberding, Women and the Female in Neoplatonism (2022) 173; d'Hoine and Martijn, All From One: A Guide to Proclus (2017) 270 NA> |
8. Plato, Theaetetus, 176b (5th cent. BCE - 4th cent. BCE) Tagged with subjects: • Metaphysics • metaphysics / metaphysical • theology, metaphysics Found in books: Fowler, Plato in the Third Sophistic (2014) 134; Lee, Moral Transformation in Greco-Roman Philosophy of Mind: Mapping the Moral Milieu of the Apostle Paul and His Diaspora Jewish Contemporaries (2020) 148, 534 ἐκεῖσε φεύγειν ὅτι τάχιστα. φυγὴ δὲ ὁμοίωσις θεῷ κατὰ τὸ δυνατόν· ὁμοίωσις δὲ δίκαιον καὶ ὅσιον μετὰ φρονήσεως γενέσθαι. ἀλλὰ γάρ, ὦ ἄριστε, οὐ πάνυ τι ῥᾴδιον πεῖσαι ὡς ἄρα οὐχ ὧν ἕνεκα οἱ πολλοί φασι δεῖν πονηρίαν μὲν φεύγειν, ἀρετὴν δὲ διώκειν, τούτων χάριν τὸ μὲν ἐπιτηδευτέον, τὸ δʼ οὔ, ἵνα δὴ μὴ κακὸς καὶ ἵνα ἀγαθὸς δοκῇ εἶναι· ταῦτα μὲν γάρ ἐστιν ὁ λεγόμενος γραῶν ὕθλος, ὡς ἐμοὶ φαίνεται· τὸ δὲ ἀληθὲς ὧδε λέγωμεν. θεὸς οὐδαμῇ NA> |
9. Plato, Timaeus, 27d6, 28a, 28b, 28c, 29a, 29a3, 29b, 30c, 31c, 37a1, 51e (5th cent. BCE - 4th cent. BCE) Tagged with subjects: • Metaphysics • Metaphysics, unmoved mover in • Power as Metaphysical Principle • Principles (in the metaphysical sense) • Subordination (and inferiority), of the female as a metaphysical principle • dualism, of Plato’s metaphysics • metaphysical • metaphysical background of ethics • metaphysics • metaphysics / metaphysical • metaphysics, Plato’s, in Timaeus • metaphysics, Plotinian • metaphysics, influence on Augustine • metaphysics/-al relevance to politics • theology, metaphysics Found in books: Corrigan and Rasimus, Gnosticism, Platonism and the Late Ancient World (2013) 8, 382, 581; Delcomminette, d’Hoine, and Gavray, Ancient Readings of Plato’s Phaedo (2015) 237; Erler et al., Authority and Authoritative Texts in the Platonist Tradition (2021) 32, 144; Fialová Hoblík and Kitzler, Hellenism, Early Judaism, and Early Christianity: Transmission and Transformation of Ideas (2022) 100; Fowler, Plato in the Third Sophistic (2014) 187, 197; Hoenig, Plato's Timaeus and the Latin Tradition (2018) 24, 251; Lee, Moral Transformation in Greco-Roman Philosophy of Mind: Mapping the Moral Milieu of the Apostle Paul and His Diaspora Jewish Contemporaries (2020) 55, 111, 144; Malherbe et al., Light from the Gentiles: Hellenistic Philosophy and Early Christianity: Collected Essays of Abraham J (2014) 818; Marmodoro and Prince, Causation and Creation in Late Antiquity (2015) 132; Schultz and Wilberding, Women and the Female in Neoplatonism (2022) 106, 223; d'Hoine and Martijn, All From One: A Guide to Proclus (2017) 108, 271, 273; Černušková, Kovacs and Plátová, Clement’s Biblical Exegesis: Proceedings of the Second Colloquium on Clement of Alexandria (2016) 288 28a ἀεί, ὂν δὲ οὐδέποτε; τὸ μὲν δὴ νοήσει μετὰ λόγου περιληπτόν, ἀεὶ κατὰ ταὐτὰ ὄν, τὸ δʼ αὖ δόξῃ μετʼ αἰσθήσεως ἀλόγου δοξαστόν, γιγνόμενον καὶ ἀπολλύμενον, ὄντως δὲ οὐδέποτε ὄν. πᾶν δὲ αὖ τὸ γιγνόμενον ὑπʼ αἰτίου τινὸς ἐξ ἀνάγκης γίγνεσθαι· παντὶ γὰρ ἀδύνατον χωρὶς αἰτίου γένεσιν σχεῖν. ὅτου μὲν οὖν ἂν ὁ δημιουργὸς πρὸς τὸ κατὰ ταὐτὰ ἔχον βλέπων ἀεί, τοιούτῳ τινὶ προσχρώμενος παραδείγματι, τὴν ἰδέαν καὶ δύναμιν αὐτοῦ ἀπεργάζηται, καλὸν ἐξ ἀνάγκης, 28b οὕτως ἀποτελεῖσθαι πᾶν· οὗ δʼ ἂν εἰς γεγονός, γεννητῷ παραδείγματι προσχρώμενος, οὐ καλόν. ὁ δὴ πᾶς οὐρανὸς —ἢ κόσμος ἢ καὶ ἄλλο ὅτι ποτὲ ὀνομαζόμενος μάλιστʼ ἂν δέχοιτο, τοῦθʼ ἡμῖν ὠνομάσθω—σκεπτέον δʼ οὖν περὶ αὐτοῦ πρῶτον, ὅπερ ὑπόκειται περὶ παντὸς ἐν ἀρχῇ δεῖν σκοπεῖν, πότερον ἦν ἀεί, γενέσεως ἀρχὴν ἔχων οὐδεμίαν, ἢ γέγονεν, ἀπʼ ἀρχῆς τινος ἀρξάμενος. γέγονεν· ὁρατὸς γὰρ ἁπτός τέ ἐστιν καὶ σῶμα ἔχων, πάντα δὲ τὰ τοιαῦτα αἰσθητά, τὰ, 28c δʼ αἰσθητά, δόξῃ περιληπτὰ μετʼ αἰσθήσεως, γιγνόμενα καὶ γεννητὰ ἐφάνη. τῷ δʼ αὖ γενομένῳ φαμὲν ὑπʼ αἰτίου τινὸς ἀνάγκην εἶναι γενέσθαι. ΤΙ. τὸν μὲν οὖν ποιητὴν καὶ πατέρα τοῦδε τοῦ παντὸς εὑρεῖν τε ἔργον καὶ εὑρόντα εἰς πάντας ἀδύνατον λέγειν· τόδε δʼ οὖν πάλιν ἐπισκεπτέον περὶ αὐτοῦ, πρὸς πότερον τῶν παραδειγμάτων ὁ τεκταινόμενος αὐτὸν, 29a ἀπηργάζετο, πότερον πρὸς τὸ κατὰ ταὐτὰ καὶ ὡσαύτως ἔχον ἢ πρὸς τὸ γεγονός. εἰ μὲν δὴ καλός ἐστιν ὅδε ὁ κόσμος ὅ τε δημιουργὸς ἀγαθός, δῆλον ὡς πρὸς τὸ ἀίδιον ἔβλεπεν· εἰ δὲ ὃ μηδʼ εἰπεῖν τινι θέμις, πρὸς γεγονός. παντὶ δὴ σαφὲς ὅτι πρὸς τὸ ἀίδιον· ὁ μὲν γὰρ κάλλιστος τῶν γεγονότων, ὁ δʼ ἄριστος τῶν αἰτίων. οὕτω δὴ γεγενημένος πρὸς τὸ λόγῳ καὶ φρονήσει περιληπτὸν καὶ κατὰ ταὐτὰ ἔχον δεδημιούργηται·, 31c οὐ δυνατόν· δεσμὸν γὰρ ἐν μέσῳ δεῖ τινα ἀμφοῖν συναγωγὸν γίγνεσθαι. δεσμῶν δὲ κάλλιστος ὃς ἂν αὑτὸν καὶ τὰ συνδούμενα ὅτι μάλιστα ἓν ποιῇ, τοῦτο δὲ πέφυκεν ἀναλογία κάλλιστα ἀποτελεῖν. ΤΙ. ὁπόταν γὰρ ἀριθμῶν τριῶν εἴτε ὄγκων, 51e δύο δὴ λεκτέον ἐκείνω, διότι χωρὶς γεγόνατον ἀνομοίως τε ἔχετον. τὸ μὲν γὰρ αὐτῶν διὰ διδαχῆς, τὸ δʼ ὑπὸ πειθοῦς ἡμῖν ἐγγίγνεται· καὶ τὸ μὲν ἀεὶ μετʼ ἀληθοῦς λόγου, τὸ δὲ ἄλογον· καὶ τὸ μὲν ἀκίνητον πειθοῖ, τὸ δὲ μεταπειστόν· καὶ τοῦ μὲν πάντα ἄνδρα μετέχειν φατέον, νοῦ δὲ θεούς, ἀνθρώπων δὲ γένος βραχύ τι. ΤΙ. τούτων δὲ οὕτως ἐχόντων, 28a and has no Becoming? And what is that which is Becoming always and never is Existent? Now the one of these is apprehensible by thought with the aid of reasoning, since it is ever uniformly existent; whereas the other is an object of opinion with the aid of unreasoning sensation, since it becomes and perishes and is never really existent. Again, everything which becomes must of necessity become owing to some Cause; for without a cause it is impossible for anything to attain becoming. But when the artificer of any object, in forming its shape and quality, keeps his gaze fixed on that which is uniform, using a model of this kind, that object, executed in this way, must of necessity, 28b be beautiful; but whenever he gazes at that which has come into existence and uses a created model, the object thus executed is not beautiful. Now the whole Heaven, or Cosmos, or if there is any other name which it specially prefers, by that let us call it,—so, be its name what it may, we must first investigate concerning it that primary question which has to be investigated at the outset in every case,—namely, whether it has existed always, having no beginning of generation, or whether it has come into existence, having begun from some beginning. It has come into existence; for it is visible and tangible and possessed of a body; and all such things are sensible, 28c and things sensible, being apprehensible by opinion with the aid of sensation, come into existence, as we saw, and are generated. And that which has come into existence must necessarily, as we say, have come into existence by reason of some Cause. Tim. Now to discover the Maker and Father of this Universe were a task indeed; and having discovered Him, to declare Him unto all men were a thing impossible. However, let us return and inquire further concerning the Cosmos,—after which of the Models did its Architect construct it? 29a Was it after that which is self-identical and uniform, or after that which has come into existence; Now if so be that this Cosmos is beautiful and its Constructor good, it is plain that he fixed his gaze on the Eternal; but if otherwise (which is an impious supposition), his gaze was on that which has come into existence. But it is clear to everyone that his gaze was on the Eternal; for the Cosmos is the fairest of all that has come into existence, and He the best of all the Causes. So having in this wise come into existence, it has been constructed after the pattern of that which is apprehensible by reason and thought and is self-identical. 31c for there must needs be some intermediary bond to connect the two. And the fairest of bonds is that which most perfectly unites into one both itself and the things which it binds together; and to effect this in the fairest manner is the natural property of proportion. Tim. For whenever the middle term of any three numbers, cubic or square, 51e Now these two Kinds must be declared to be two, because they have come into existence separately and are unlike in condition. For the one of them arises in us by teaching, the other by persuasion; and the one is always in company with true reasoning, whereas the other is irrational; and the one is immovable by persuasion, whereas the other is alterable by persuasion; and of the one we must assert that every man partakes, but of Reason only the gods and but a small class of men. Tim. This being so, we must agree that One Kind, |
10. Aristotle, Soul, 2.1, 3.5 (4th cent. BCE - 4th cent. BCE) Tagged with subjects: • Aristotle, Metaphysics • Principles (in the metaphysical sense) • identity, metaphysics of • theology, metaphysics Found in books: Delcomminette, d’Hoine, and Gavray, Ancient Readings of Plato’s Phaedo (2015) 167; Fowler, Plato in the Third Sophistic (2014) 187; Gerson and Wilberding, The New Cambridge Companion to Plotinus (2022) 120; Seaford, Wilkins, Wright, Selfhood and the Soul: Essays on Ancient Thought and Literature in Honour of Christopher Gill (2017) 83 NA> |
11. Aristotle, Metaphysics, 7.3, 12.7, 980a21 (4th cent. BCE - 4th cent. BCE) Tagged with subjects: • Aristotle, Metaphysics • Metaphysics • Metaphysics, unmoved mover in • identity, metaphysics of Found in books: Fowler, Plato in the Third Sophistic (2014) 206; Gerson and Wilberding, The New Cambridge Companion to Plotinus (2022) 120, 181, 194, 208; Joosse, Olympiodorus of Alexandria: Exegete, Teacher, Platonic Philosopher (2021) 34; Marmodoro and Prince, Causation and Creation in Late Antiquity (2015) 132; Seaford, Wilkins, Wright, Selfhood and the Soul: Essays on Ancient Thought and Literature in Honour of Christopher Gill (2017) 83; Tsouni, Antiochus and Peripatetic Ethics (2019) 142 NA> |
12. Anon., 1 Enoch, 9.5 (3rd cent. BCE - 2nd cent. BCE) Tagged with subjects: • metaphysical • metaphysics • prepositional metaphysics Found in books: Garcia, On Human Nature in Early Judaism: Creation, Composition, and Condition (2021) 146; Novenson, Monotheism and Christology in Greco-Roman Antiquity (2020) 146 9.5 ages, and Thy name holy and glorious and blessed unto all the ages! Thou hast made all things, and power over all things hast Thou: and all things are naked and open in Thy sight, and Thou seest all |
13. Philo of Alexandria, Allegorical Interpretation, 1.40 (1st cent. BCE - 1st cent. CE) Tagged with subjects: • metaphysical • metaphysics Found in books: Garcia, On Human Nature in Early Judaism: Creation, Composition, and Condition (2021) 150; Horkey, Cosmos in the Ancient World (2019) 286 1.40 By what then were these subordinate parts inspired? beyond all question by the mind; for of the qualities which the mind has received form God, it gives a share to the irrational portion of the soul, so that the mind is vivified by God, and the irrational part of the soul by the mind; for the mind is as it were a god to the irrational part of the soul, for which reason Moses did not hesitate to call it "the god of Pharaoh." |
14. New Testament, John, 1.1-1.18 (1st cent. CE - 1st cent. CE) Tagged with subjects: • Metaphysics • metaphysical • metaphysics • prepositional metaphysics Found in books: Corrigan and Rasimus, Gnosticism, Platonism and the Late Ancient World (2013) 437; Novenson, Monotheism and Christology in Greco-Roman Antiquity (2020) 145; Černušková, Kovacs and Plátová, Clement’s Biblical Exegesis: Proceedings of the Second Colloquium on Clement of Alexandria (2016) 277, 285, 288 1.1 ΕΝ ΑΡΧΗ ἦν ὁ λόγος, καὶ ὁ λόγος ἦν πρὸς τὸν θεόν, καὶ θεὸς ἦν ὁ λόγος. 1.2 Οὗτος ἦν ἐν ἀρχῇ πρὸς τὸν θεόν. 1.3 πάντα διʼ αὐτοῦ ἐγένετο, καὶ χωρὶς αὐτοῦ ἐγένετο οὐδὲ ἕν. 1.4 ὃ γέγονεν ἐν αὐτῷ ζωὴ ἦν, καὶ ἡ ζωὴ ἦν τὸ φῶς τῶν ἀνθρώπων·, 1.5 καὶ τὸ φῶς ἐν τῇ σκοτίᾳ φαίνει, καὶ ἡ σκοτία αὐτὸ οὐ κατέλαβεν. 1.6 Ἐγένετο ἄνθρωπος ἀπεσταλμένος παρὰ θεοῦ, ὄνομα αὐτῷ Ἰωάνης·, 1.7 οὗτος ἦλθεν εἰς μαρτυρίαν, ἵνα μαρτυρήσῃ περὶ τοῦ φωτός, ἵνα πάντες πιστεύσωσιν διʼ αὐτοῦ. 1.8 οὐκ ἦν ἐκεῖνος τὸ φῶς, ἀλλʼ ἵνα μαρτυρήσῃ περὶ τοῦ φωτός. 1.9 Ἦν τὸ φῶς τὸ ἀληθινὸν ὃ φωτίζει πάντα ἄνθρωπον ἐρχόμενον εἰς τὸν κόσμον. 1.10 ἐν τῷ κόσμῳ ἦν, καὶ ὁ κόσμος διʼ αὐτοῦ ἐγένετο, καὶ ὁ κόσμος αὐτὸν οὐκ ἔγνω. 1.11 Εἰς τὰ ἴδια ἦλθεν, καὶ οἱ ἴδιοι αὐτὸν οὐ παρέλαβον. 1.12 ὅσοι δὲ ἔλαβον αὐτόν, ἔδωκεν αὐτοῖς ἐξουσίαν τέκνα θεοῦ γενέσθαι, τοῖς πιστεύουσιν εἰς τὸ ὄνομα αὐτοῦ, 1.13 οἳ οὐκ ἐξ αἱμάτων οὐδὲ ἐκ θελήματος σαρκὸς οὐδὲ ἐκ θελήματος ἀνδρὸς ἀλλʼ ἐκ θεοῦ ἐγεννήθησαν. 1.14 Καὶ ὁ λόγος σὰρξ ἐγένετο καὶ ἐσκήνωσεν ἐν ἡμῖν, καὶ ἐθεασάμεθα τὴν δόξαν αὐτοῦ, δόξαν ὡς μονογενοῦς παρὰ πατρός, πλήρης χάριτος καὶ ἀληθείας·?̔, 1.15 Ἰωάνης μαρτυρεῖ περὶ αὐτοῦ καὶ κέκραγεν λέγων — οὗτος ἦν ὁ εἰπών — Ὁ ὀπίσω μου ἐρχόμενος ἔμπροσθέν μου γέγονεν, ὅτι πρῶτός μου ἦν·̓, 1.16 ὅτι ἐκ τοῦ πληρώματος αὐτοῦ ἡμεῖς πάντες ἐλάβομεν, καὶ χάριν ἀντὶ χάριτος·, 1.17 ὅτι ὁ νόμος διὰ Μωυσέως ἐδόθη, ἡ χάρις καὶ ἡ ἀλήθεια διὰ Ἰησοῦ Χριστοῦ ἐγένετο. 1.18 θεὸν οὐδεὶς ἑώρακεν πώποτε· μονογενὴς θεὸς ὁ ὢν εἰς τὸν κόλπον τοῦ πατρὸς ἐκεῖνος ἐξηγήσατο. 1.1 In the beginning was the Word, and the Word was with God, and the Word was God. 1.2 The same was in the beginning with God. 1.3 All things were made through him. Without him was not anything made that has been made. 1.4 In him was life, and the life was the light of men. " 1.5 The light shines in the darkness, and the darkness hasnt overcome it.", 1.6 There came a man, sent from God, whose name was John. 1.7 The same came as a witness, that he might testify about the light, that all might believe through him. 1.8 He was not the light, but was sent that he might testify about the light. 1.9 The true light that enlightens everyone was coming into the world. " 1.10 He was in the world, and the world was made through him, and the world didnt recognize him.", " 1.11 He came to his own, and those who were his own didnt receive him.", " 1.12 But as many as received him, to them he gave the right to become Gods children, to those who believe in his name:", 1.13 who were born not of blood, nor of the will of the flesh, nor of the will of man, but of God. 1.14 The Word became flesh, and lived among us. We saw his glory, such glory as of the one and only Son of the Father, full of grace and truth. 1.15 John testified about him. He cried out, saying, "This was he of whom I said, He who comes after me has surpassed me, for he was before me.", 1.16 From his fullness we all received grace upon grace. 1.17 For the law was given through Moses. Grace and truth came through Jesus Christ. 1.18 No one has seen God at any time. The one and only Son, who is in the bosom of the Father, he has declared him. |
15. Plutarch, On Isis And Osiris, 382d (1st cent. CE - 2nd cent. CE) Tagged with subjects: • Aristotle, Metaphysics • System (σύστηµα/συστήµατα), of Philosophy, of doctrine / metaphysical Found in books: Erler et al., Authority and Authoritative Texts in the Platonist Tradition (2021) 164; Motta and Petrucci, Isagogical Crossroads from the Early Imperial Age to the End of Antiquity (2022) 104 382d they lay it away and guard it, unseen and untouched. But the robes of Isis they use many times over; for in use those things that are perceptible and ready at hand afford many disclosures of themselves and opportunities to view them as they are changed about in various ways. But the apperception of the conceptual, the pure, and the simple, shining through the soul like a flash of lightning, affords an opportunity to touch and see it but once. For this reason Plato and Aristotle call this part of philosophy the epoptic or mystic part, inasmuch as those who have passed beyond these conjectural and confused matters of all sorts by means of Reason proceed by leaps and bounds to that primary, simple, and immaterial principle; |
16. Plutarch, On The Delays of Divine Vengeance, 550d, 550e (1st cent. CE - 2nd cent. CE) Tagged with subjects: • demiurge, in Plotinus' metaphysics • metaphysics / metaphysical Found in books: Lee, Moral Transformation in Greco-Roman Philosophy of Mind: Mapping the Moral Milieu of the Apostle Paul and His Diaspora Jewish Contemporaries (2020) 140, 148; Marmodoro and Prince, Causation and Creation in Late Antiquity (2015) 53 NA> |
17. Albinus, Introduction To Plato, 6.151.4 (2nd cent. CE - 2nd cent. CE) Tagged with subjects: • One (metaphysical) • One (metaphysical), One-Being • System (σύστηµα/συστήµατα), of Philosophy, of doctrine / metaphysical • metaphysics • metaphysics / metaphysical Found in books: Lee, Moral Transformation in Greco-Roman Philosophy of Mind: Mapping the Moral Milieu of the Apostle Paul and His Diaspora Jewish Contemporaries (2020) 122; Malherbe et al., Light from the Gentiles: Hellenistic Philosophy and Early Christianity: Collected Essays of Abraham J (2014) 818; Motta and Petrucci, Isagogical Crossroads from the Early Imperial Age to the End of Antiquity (2022) 100; Tanaseanu-Döbler and von Alvensleben, Athens II: Athens in Late Antiquity (2020) 305 NA> |
18. Alcinous, Handbook of Platonism, 4.7, 14.4 (2nd cent. CE - 2nd cent. CE) Tagged with subjects: • Metaphysics • demiurge, in Plotinus' metaphysics • metaphysic of mind • metaphysics / metaphysical Found in books: Fowler, Plato in the Third Sophistic (2014) 206; Lee, Moral Transformation in Greco-Roman Philosophy of Mind: Mapping the Moral Milieu of the Apostle Paul and His Diaspora Jewish Contemporaries (2020) 133, 135, 136; Marmodoro and Prince, Causation and Creation in Late Antiquity (2015) 53; Osborne, Irenaeus of Lyons (2001) 36 NA> |
19. Irenaeus, Refutation of All Heresies, 1.2.4 (2nd cent. CE - 3rd cent. CE) Tagged with subjects: • Metaphysics • metaphysics Found in books: Corrigan and Rasimus, Gnosticism, Platonism and the Late Ancient World (2013) 420; Novenson, Monotheism and Christology in Greco-Roman Antiquity (2020) 259 1.2.4 The Father afterwards produces, in his own image, by means of Monogenes, the above-mentioned Horos, without conjunction, masculo-feminine. For they maintain that sometimes the Father acts in conjunction with Sige, but that at other times he shows himself independent both of male and female. They term this Horos both Stauros and Lytrotes, and Carpistes, and Horothetes, and Metagoges. And by this Horos they declare that Sophia was purified and established, while she was also restored to her proper conjunction. For her enthymesis (or inborn idea) having been taken away from her, along with its supervening passion, she herself certainly remained within the Pleroma; but her enthymesis, with its passion, was separated from her by Horos, fenced off, and expelled from that circle. This enthymesis was, no doubt, a spiritual substance, possessing some of the natural tendencies of an AEon, but at the same time shapeless and without form, because it had received nothing. And on this account they say that it was an imbecile and feminine production. |
20. Numenius of Apamea, Fragments, 17 (2nd cent. CE - 2nd cent. CE) Tagged with subjects: • Metaphysics • theology, metaphysics Found in books: Corrigan and Rasimus, Gnosticism, Platonism and the Late Ancient World (2013) 386; Fowler, Plato in the Third Sophistic (2014) 187 NA> |
21. Diogenes Laertius, Lives of The Philosophers, 7.135-7.136 (3rd cent. CE - 3rd cent. CE) Tagged with subjects: • Metaphysics • metaphysics Found in books: Corrigan and Rasimus, Gnosticism, Platonism and the Late Ancient World (2013) 386; Long, From Epicurus to Epictetus Studies in Hellenistic and Roman Philosophy (2006) 239 7.135 Body is defined by Apollodorus in his Physics as that which is extended in three dimensions, length, breadth, and depth. This is also called solid body. But surface is the extremity of a solid body, or that which has length and breadth only without depth. That surface exists not only in our thought but also in reality is maintained by Posidonius in the third book of his Celestial Phenomena. A line is the extremity of a surface or length without breadth, or that which has length alone. A point is the extremity of a line, the smallest possible mark or dot.God is one and the same with Reason, Fate, and Zeus; he is also called by many other names. 7.136 In the beginning he was by himself; he transformed the whole of substance through air into water, and just as in animal generation the seed has a moist vehicle, so in cosmic moisture God, who is the seminal reason of the universe, remains behind in the moisture as such an agent, adapting matter to himself with a view to the next stage of creation. Thereupon he created first of all the four elements, fire, water, air, earth. They are discussed by Zeno in his treatise On the Whole, by Chrysippus in the first book of his Physics, and by Archedemus in a work On Elements. An element is defined as that from which particular things first come to be at their birth and into which they are finally resolved. |
22. Origen, On First Principles, 4.4.8 (3rd cent. CE - 3rd cent. CE) Tagged with subjects: • Metaphysics • metaphysics Found in books: Fialová Hoblík and Kitzler, Hellenism, Early Judaism, and Early Christianity: Transmission and Transformation of Ideas (2022) 77; Fowler, Plato in the Third Sophistic (2014) 206 NA> |
23. Plotinus, Enneads, 2.9, 3.8, 5.5, 5.8 (3rd cent. CE - 3rd cent. CE) Tagged with subjects: • Metaphysics • One (metaphysical) • Power as Metaphysical Principle • creation, metaphysics • metaphysics • metaphysics / metaphysical Found in books: Corrigan and Rasimus, Gnosticism, Platonism and the Late Ancient World (2013) 326, 420, 427, 428, 468, 504, 506, 581; Lee, Moral Transformation in Greco-Roman Philosophy of Mind: Mapping the Moral Milieu of the Apostle Paul and His Diaspora Jewish Contemporaries (2020) 122; Novenson, Monotheism and Christology in Greco-Roman Antiquity (2020) 252; Schultz and Wilberding, Women and the Female in Neoplatonism (2022) 54; Tanaseanu-Döbler and von Alvensleben, Athens II: Athens in Late Antiquity (2020) 243; Yates and Dupont, The Bible in Christian North Africa: Part II: Consolidation of the Canon to the Arab Conquest (ca. 393 to 650 CE). (2023) 108 NA> |
24. Porphyry, Life of Plotinus, 9.12-9.16 (3rd cent. CE - 4th cent. CE) Tagged with subjects: • Metaphysics • Subordination (and inferiority), of the female as a metaphysical principle Found in books: Corrigan and Rasimus, Gnosticism, Platonism and the Late Ancient World (2013) 468, 506; Motta and Petrucci, Isagogical Crossroads from the Early Imperial Age to the End of Antiquity (2022) 106; Schultz and Wilberding, Women and the Female in Neoplatonism (2022) 60 NA> |
25. Marinus, Vita Proclus, 13, 28 (4th cent. CE - 5th cent. CE) Tagged with subjects: • Commentary on Aristotles Metaphysics • Metaphysics • One (metaphysical) • metaphysics/-al in relation to theology • theology, metaphysics Found in books: Fowler, Plato in the Third Sophistic (2014) 64; Tanaseanu-Döbler and von Alvensleben, Athens II: Athens in Late Antiquity (2020) 28; d'Hoine and Martijn, All From One: A Guide to Proclus (2017) 29, 170, 213 13 During this season of less than two years, with his teacher, Proclus read all of Aristotles treatises on logic, ethics, politics, physics, and on the science which rises above all these, theology. Solidly outfitted with these studies, which so to speak, are a kind of preparatory initiation or lesser mysteries, Syrianus led Proclus to the Greater Mysteries of Plato, proceeding in an orderly manner, and not, as says the Oracle, "jumping over the threshold." So Syrianus led Proclus to direct and immediate vision of the really divine mysteries contained in this philosopher, for when the eyes of the soul are no longer obscured as by a mist, reason, freed from sensation, may cast firm glances into the distance. By an intense and unresting labor by day and night, he succeeded in recording in writing, along with his own critical remarks, the doctrine which he heard discussed, and of which he finally made a synoptic outline, making such progress that at the age of twenty-eight years, he had composed many treatises, among others a Commentary on the Timaeus, written with utmost elegance and science. Through these prolonged and inspiring studies, to science he added virtue, increasing the moral beauty of his nature. 28 But since, as I said before, by his studies on this subject, he had acquired a still greater and more perfect virtue, namely the theurgic, passing beyond the theoretic step, he did not conform his life exclusively to one of the two characteristics suitable to divine beings, but to both: not only did he direct his thoughts upward to the divine, but by a providential faculty which was not merely social, he cared for those things which were lower. He practiced the Chaldean prayer-meetings and conferences, and even employed the art of moving the divine tops. He was a believer in these practices, in unpremeditated responses, and other such divinations, which he had learned from Asklepigenia, daughter of Plutarch, to whom exclusively her father had confided and taught the mystic rites preserved by Nestorius, and the whole theurgic science. Even before that, according to the prescribed order, and purified by the Chaldean lustrations, the philosopher had, as epoptic initiate, witnessed the apparitions of Hecate under a luminous form, as he himself has mentioned in a special booklet. He had the power of producing rains by activating, at the right time, a particular rite, and was able to deliver Attica from a terrible drought. He knew how to foresee earthquakes, he had experimented with the divinatory power of the tripod, and had himself uttered verses prophetic about his own destiny. When 40 years old, he felt that in a dream he had uttered the following verses: "Here broods an immortal splendor, that is supercelestial, which has sprung from the consecrated spring, and whence streams a fiery light!" At the beginning of his 42nd year, he so seemed to be shouting the following verses: "I am possessed by a spirit which breathes into me the force of fire, which, enfolding and entrancing my reason in a whirl of flame, flies toward the aether, and with its immortal vibrations reechoes in the starry vaults!" Besides, in a dream he had clearly seen that he belonged to the Hermetic Chain; and, on the authority of a dream, he was convinced that his was the reincarnated soul of the Pythagorean Nicomachus. |
26. Proclus, In Platonis Timaeum Commentarii, 1.7.13-1.7.16, 2.302 (5th cent. CE - 5th cent. CE) Tagged with subjects: • Commentary on Aristotles Metaphysics • dualism, of Plato’s metaphysics • metaphysics • metaphysics, Apuleius’s treatment of • metaphysics, Plato’s, in Timaeus • metaphysics, in Calcidius’s commentary • metaphysics, in Platonic curriculum • metaphysics, influence on Augustine • metaphysics, trinitarian • spiritual/metaphysical self-motion Found in books: Erler et al., Authority and Authoritative Texts in the Platonist Tradition (2021) 223; Hoenig, Plato's Timaeus and the Latin Tradition (2018) 107, 144, 208, 249, 250, 251, 252, 253, 254, 255, 256, 257, 258, 259, 260, 261, 262, 263, 264, 265, 266, 267, 268, 269, 270, 279; d'Hoine and Martijn, All From One: A Guide to Proclus (2017) 29, 126 NA> |
27. Proclus, Institutio Theologica, 26, 29-32, 35, 38 (5th cent. CE - 5th cent. CE) Tagged with subjects: • Proclus Diadochus, survey of Proclus’ metaphysics • multiplicity (metaphysical) • spiritual/metaphysical self-motion • unity, metaphysical unity Found in books: Ayres Champion and Crawford, The Intellectual World of Late Antique Christianity: Reshaping Classical Traditions (2023) 596, 597; Tanaseanu-Döbler and von Alvensleben, Athens II: Athens in Late Antiquity (2020) 328; d'Hoine and Martijn, All From One: A Guide to Proclus (2017) 54, 55, 69 NA> |
28. Proclus, Theologia Platonica ( ), 1.1 (5th cent. CE - 5th cent. CE) Tagged with subjects: • Metaphysics • metaphysics Found in books: Corrigan and Rasimus, Gnosticism, Platonism and the Late Ancient World (2013) 549; Erler et al., Authority and Authoritative Texts in the Platonist Tradition (2021) 213, 214, 223, 243, 244 NA> |
29. Olympiodorus The Younger of Alexandria, In Platonis Gorgiam Commentaria, 34.3, 47.3 (6th cent. CE - 6th cent. CE) Tagged with subjects: • Metaphysics, simplified • Principles (in the metaphysical sense) • theology, metaphysics Found in books: Delcomminette, d’Hoine, and Gavray, Ancient Readings of Plato’s Phaedo (2015) 273, 275; Fowler, Plato in the Third Sophistic (2014) 82; Joosse, Olympiodorus of Alexandria: Exegete, Teacher, Platonic Philosopher (2021) 2, 217 NA> |
30. Anon, Anonymous Prolegomena To Plato'S Philosophy, 26.13-26.44 Tagged with subjects: • Aristotle, Metaphysics • Metaphysics • System (σύστηµα/συστήµατα), of Philosophy, of doctrine / metaphysical • metaphysics/-al reading of the Parmenides Found in books: Corrigan and Rasimus, Gnosticism, Platonism and the Late Ancient World (2013) 544, 555; Joosse, Olympiodorus of Alexandria: Exegete, Teacher, Platonic Philosopher (2021) 34; Motta and Petrucci, Isagogical Crossroads from the Early Imperial Age to the End of Antiquity (2022) 99, 107; d'Hoine and Martijn, All From One: A Guide to Proclus (2017) 31, 112 NA> |
31. Anon., Chaldean Oracles, 5, 37 Tagged with subjects: • Metaphysics • Metaphysics, unmoved mover in Found in books: Corrigan and Rasimus, Gnosticism, Platonism and the Late Ancient World (2013) 386, 537; Marmodoro and Prince, Causation and Creation in Late Antiquity (2015) 132 NA> |
32. Simplicius of Cilicia, In Aristotelis Physicorum Libros Commentaria, 181.10-181.12, 181.17 (missingth cent. CE - 5th cent. CE) Tagged with subjects: • Aristotle, Metaphysics • metaphysic of mind Found in books: Erler et al., Authority and Authoritative Texts in the Platonist Tradition (2021) 163; Osborne, Irenaeus of Lyons (2001) 38 NA> |