Home About Network of subjects Linked subjects heatmap Book indices included Search by subject Search by reference Browse subjects Browse texts

Tiresias: The Ancient Mediterranean Religions Source Database



4479
Diogenes Laertius, Lives Of The Philosophers, 1.14-1.16
NaN
NaN
NaN


Intertexts (texts cited often on the same page as the searched text):

5 results
1. Cicero, Academica, 1.15 (2nd cent. BCE - 1st cent. BCE)

1.15. Tum Varro ita exorsus est: 'Socrates mihi videtur, id quod constat inter omnes, primus a rebus occultis et ab ipsa natura involutis, in quibus omnibus *d omnes ante eum philosophi occupati fuerunt, avocavisse philosophiam et ad vitam communem adduxisse, ut de virtutibus et de vitiis omninoque de de 1 om. *d bonis rebus et malis quaereret, caelestia autem vel procul esse a nostra cognitione censeret vel, si maxime cognita essent, nihil tamen ad bene vivendum.
2. Cicero, Tusculan Disputations, 5.10-5.11 (2nd cent. BCE - 1st cent. BCE)

5.10. Nec vero Pythagoras nominis solum inventor, sed rerum etiam ipsarum amplificator amplicator G fuit. qui cum post cum post ( eras. q) K hunc Phliasium sermonem in Italiam venisset, exornavit eam Graeciam, quae magna dicta est, et privatim et publice praestantissumis et institutis et artibus. cuius de disciplina aliud tempus fuerit fortasse dicendi. sed ab antiqua philosophia usque ad Socratem, qui Archelaum, Anaxagorae discipulum, audierat, numeri motusque tractabantur, et unde omnia orerentur orarentur K quove reciderent, recederent X corr. V 1 aut c s studioseque ab is siderum magnitudines intervalla cursus currus G 1 antiquirebantur G ( alt. i e corr. 2 ) anquirebantur et cuncta caelestia. Socrates autem primus philosophiam devocavit e caelo et in urbibus conlocavit et in domus domos s ac fort. V 1 (u e corr. c ) domibus Gr. etiam introduxit et coëgit de vita et moribus rebusque bonis et malis quaerere. 5.11. cuius multiplex ratio disputandi rerumque varietas et ingenii magnitudo Platonis memoria et litteris consecrata plura genera effecit effecit s efficit X dissentientium philosophorum, e quibus nos id potissimum consecuti consecuti con del. V 2 sumus, quo Socratem usum arbitrabamur, arbitramur V 2 s ut nostram ipsi sententiam tegeremus, errore alios levaremus et in omni disputatione, quid esset simillimum veri, quaereremus. quaeremus G 1 K quem morem moyerem G 2 cum Carneades acutissime copiosissimeque tenuisset, fecimus et alias saepe et nuper in Tusculano, ut ad eam eam ( del. c ) R consuetudinem disputaremus. et quadridui quidem sermonem superioribus ad ad a R missimus G 1 K te perscriptum libris misimus, quinto autem die cum eodem in loco consedissemus, sic est propositum, de quo disputaremus:
3. Mishnah, Avot, 1 (1st cent. CE - 3rd cent. CE)

4. Sextus, Outlines of Pyrrhonism, 1.209-1.241 (2nd cent. CE - 3rd cent. CE)

5. Diogenes Laertius, Lives of The Philosophers, 1.13, 1.15-1.16, 2.2, 9.5, 9.20-9.21, 9.61, 9.71-9.73 (3rd cent. CE - 3rd cent. CE)

2.2. He was the first to draw on a map the outline of land and sea, and he constructed a globe as well.His exposition of his doctrines took the form of a summary which no doubt came into the hands, among others, of Apollodorus of Athens. He says in his Chronology that in the second year of the 58th Olympiad Anaximander was sixty-four, and that he died not long afterwards. Thus he flourished almost at the same time as Polycrates the tyrant of Samos. There is a story that the boys laughed at his singing, and that, when he heard of it, he rejoined, Then to please the boys I must improve my singing.There is another Anaximander, also of Miletus, a historian who wrote in the Ionic dialect. 9.5. He was exceptional from his boyhood; for when a youth he used to say that he knew nothing, although when he was grown up he claimed that he knew everything. He was nobody's pupil, but he declared that he inquired of himself, and learned everything from himself. Some, however, had said that he had been a pupil of Xenophanes, as we learn from Sotion, who also tells us that Ariston in his book On Heraclitus declares that he was cured of the dropsy and died of another disease. And Hippobotus has the same story.As to the work which passes as his, it is a continuous treatise On Nature, but is divided into three discourses, one on the universe, another on politics, and a third on theology. 9.20. He also said that the mass of things falls short of thought; and again that our encounters with tyrants should be as few, or else as pleasant, as possible. When Empedocles remarked to him that it is impossible to find a wise man, Naturally, he replied, for it takes a wise man to recognize a wise man. Sotion says that he was the first to maintain that all things are incognizable, but Sotion is in error.One of his poems is The Founding of Colophon, and another The Settlement of a Colony at Elea in Italy, making 2000 lines in all. He flourished about the 60th Olympiad. That he buried his sons with his own hands like Anaxagoras is stated by Demetrius of Phalerum in his work On Old Age and by Panaetius the Stoic in his book of Cheerfulness. He is believed to have been sold into slavery by [... and to have been set free by] the Pythagoreans Parmeniscus and Orestades: so Favorinus in the first book of his Memorabilia. There was also another Xenophanes, of Lesbos, an iambic poet.Such were the sporadic philosophers. 9.21. 3. PARMENIDESParmenides, a native of Elea, son of Pyres, was a pupil of Xenophanes (Theophrastus in his Epitome makes him a pupil of Anaximander). Parmenides, however, though he was instructed by Xenophanes, was no follower of his. According to Sotion he also associated with Ameinias the Pythagorean, who was the son of Diochaetas and a worthy gentleman though poor. This Ameinias he was more inclined to follow, and on his death he built a shrine to him, being himself of illustrious birth and possessed of great wealth; moreover it was Ameinias and not Xenophanes who led him to adopt the peaceful life of a student.He was the first to declare that the earth is spherical and is situated in the centre of the universe. He held that there were two elements, fire and earth, and that the former discharged the function of a craftsman, the latter of his material. 9.61. 11. PYRRHOPyrrho of Elis was the son of Pleistarchus, as Diocles relates. According to Apollodorus in his Chronology, he was first a painter; then he studied under Stilpo's son Bryson: thus Alexander in his Successions of Philosophers. Afterwards he joined Anaxarchus, whom he accompanied on his travels everywhere so that he even forgathered with the Indian Gymnosophists and with the Magi. This led him to adopt a most noble philosophy, to quote Ascanius of Abdera, taking the form of agnosticism and suspension of judgement. He denied that anything was honourable or dishonourable, just or unjust. And so, universally, he held that there is nothing really existent, but custom and convention govern human action; for no single thing is in itself any more this than that. 9.71. Some call Homer the founder of this school, for to the same questions he more than anyone else is always giving different answers at different times, and is never definite or dogmatic about the answer. The maxims of the Seven Wise Men, too, they call sceptical; for instance, Observe the Golden Mean, and A pledge is a curse at one's elbow, meaning that whoever plights his troth steadfastly and trustfully brings a curse on his own head. Sceptically minded, again, were Archilochus and Euripides, for Archilochus says:Man's soul, O Glaucus, son of Leptines,Is but as one short day that Zeus sends down.And Euripides:Great God! how can they say poor mortal menHave minds and think? Hang we not on thy will?Do we not what it pleaseth thee to wish? 9.72. Furthermore, they find Xenophanes, Zeno of Elea, and Democritus to be sceptics: Xenophanes because he says,Clear truth hath no man seen nor e'er shall knowand Zeno because he would destroy motion, saying, A moving body moves neither where it is nor where it is not; Democritus because he rejects qualities, saying, Opinion says hot or cold, but the reality is atoms and empty space, and again, of a truth we know nothing, for truth is in a well. Plato, too, leaves the truth to gods and sons of gods, and seeks after the probable explanation. Euripides says: 9.73. Who knoweth if to die be but to live,And that called life by mortals be but death?So too Empedocles:So to these mortal may not list nor lookNor yet conceive them in his mind;and before that:Each believes naught but his experience.And even Heraclitus: Let us not conjecture on deepest questions what is likely. Then again Hippocrates showed himself two-sided and but human. And before them all Homer:Pliant is the tongue of mortals; numberless the tales within it;andAmple is of words the pasture, hither thither widely ranging;andAnd the saying which thou sayest, back it cometh later on thee,where he is speaking of the equal value of contradictory sayings.


Subjects of this text:

subject book bibliographic info
academy Vogt, Pyrrhonian Skepticism in Diogenes Laertius (2015) 112
aenesidemus Vogt, Pyrrhonian Skepticism in Diogenes Laertius (2015) 75, 112
alexandria Vogt, Pyrrhonian Skepticism in Diogenes Laertius (2015) 112
anaxagoras Cornelli, In Search of Pythagoreanism: Pythagoreanism as an Historiographical Category (2013) 17
anaximander Cornelli, In Search of Pythagoreanism: Pythagoreanism as an Historiographical Category (2013) 17
anaximenes Cornelli, In Search of Pythagoreanism: Pythagoreanism as an Historiographical Category (2013) 17
archilochus Vogt, Pyrrhonian Skepticism in Diogenes Laertius (2015) 110
bernabé, a. Cornelli, In Search of Pythagoreanism: Pythagoreanism as an Historiographical Category (2013) 17
cicero, on socrates Wolfsdorf, Early Greek Ethics (2020) 54
cornford, f.m. Cornelli, In Search of Pythagoreanism: Pythagoreanism as an Historiographical Category (2013) 17
democritus Cornelli, In Search of Pythagoreanism: Pythagoreanism as an Historiographical Category (2013) 17; Vogt, Pyrrhonian Skepticism in Diogenes Laertius (2015) 110
diogenes laertius Cornelli, In Search of Pythagoreanism: Pythagoreanism as an Historiographical Category (2013) 17; Vogt, Pyrrhonian Skepticism in Diogenes Laertius (2015) 75, 110, 112
empedocles Vogt, Pyrrhonian Skepticism in Diogenes Laertius (2015) 110
epicurus Cornelli, In Search of Pythagoreanism: Pythagoreanism as an Historiographical Category (2013) 17
euripides Vogt, Pyrrhonian Skepticism in Diogenes Laertius (2015) 110
guthrie, w.k.c. Cornelli, In Search of Pythagoreanism: Pythagoreanism as an Historiographical Category (2013) 17
heraclitus Vogt, Pyrrhonian Skepticism in Diogenes Laertius (2015) 75, 110, 112
homer Vogt, Pyrrhonian Skepticism in Diogenes Laertius (2015) 110
kahn, c.h. Cornelli, In Search of Pythagoreanism: Pythagoreanism as an Historiographical Category (2013) 17
leucippus Cornelli, In Search of Pythagoreanism: Pythagoreanism as an Historiographical Category (2013) 17
lists Bickerman and Tropper, Studies in Jewish and Christian History (2007) 537
natural philosophy, socrates and prior tradition Wolfsdorf, Early Greek Ethics (2020) 54
oral law Bickerman and Tropper, Studies in Jewish and Christian History (2007) 537
parmenides Cornelli, In Search of Pythagoreanism: Pythagoreanism as an Historiographical Category (2013) 17; Vogt, Pyrrhonian Skepticism in Diogenes Laertius (2015) 75
pharisees Bickerman and Tropper, Studies in Jewish and Christian History (2007) 537
philosophers Bickerman and Tropper, Studies in Jewish and Christian History (2007) 537
phoenicians Bickerman and Tropper, Studies in Jewish and Christian History (2007) 537
plato Cornelli, In Search of Pythagoreanism: Pythagoreanism as an Historiographical Category (2013) 17; Vogt, Pyrrhonian Skepticism in Diogenes Laertius (2015) 110
pyrrho Vogt, Pyrrhonian Skepticism in Diogenes Laertius (2015) 75
pyrrhonism Vogt, Pyrrhonian Skepticism in Diogenes Laertius (2015) 75, 112
pyrrhonists Vogt, Pyrrhonian Skepticism in Diogenes Laertius (2015) 112
pythagoras Cornelli, In Search of Pythagoreanism: Pythagoreanism as an Historiographical Category (2013) 17
pythagoras and pythagoreans Bickerman and Tropper, Studies in Jewish and Christian History (2007) 537
reality Vogt, Pyrrhonian Skepticism in Diogenes Laertius (2015) 110
rome, law Bickerman and Tropper, Studies in Jewish and Christian History (2007) 537
sassi, m.m. Cornelli, In Search of Pythagoreanism: Pythagoreanism as an Historiographical Category (2013) 17
schools Bickerman and Tropper, Studies in Jewish and Christian History (2007) 537
seven sages Bickerman and Tropper, Studies in Jewish and Christian History (2007) 537; Vogt, Pyrrhonian Skepticism in Diogenes Laertius (2015) 110
sextus empiricus Vogt, Pyrrhonian Skepticism in Diogenes Laertius (2015) 75, 110
shechemites Bickerman and Tropper, Studies in Jewish and Christian History (2007) 537
skepticism, academic skepticism Vogt, Pyrrhonian Skepticism in Diogenes Laertius (2015) 112
skepticism Vogt, Pyrrhonian Skepticism in Diogenes Laertius (2015) 110, 112
socrates, and natural philosophical tradition Wolfsdorf, Early Greek Ethics (2020) 54
socrates Bickerman and Tropper, Studies in Jewish and Christian History (2007) 537; Cornelli, In Search of Pythagoreanism: Pythagoreanism as an Historiographical Category (2013) 17
sotion Vogt, Pyrrhonian Skepticism in Diogenes Laertius (2015) 112
stoicism Bickerman and Tropper, Studies in Jewish and Christian History (2007) 537
timon Vogt, Pyrrhonian Skepticism in Diogenes Laertius (2015) 75
xenophanes Cornelli, In Search of Pythagoreanism: Pythagoreanism as an Historiographical Category (2013) 17; Vogt, Pyrrhonian Skepticism in Diogenes Laertius (2015) 75, 110, 112
zeno Bickerman and Tropper, Studies in Jewish and Christian History (2007) 537
zeno of elea' Cornelli, In Search of Pythagoreanism: Pythagoreanism as an Historiographical Category (2013) 17
zeno of elea Vogt, Pyrrhonian Skepticism in Diogenes Laertius (2015) 110
zoroaster Bickerman and Tropper, Studies in Jewish and Christian History (2007) 537