Home About Network of subjects Linked subjects heatmap Book indices included Search by subject Search by reference Browse subjects Browse texts

Tiresias: The Ancient Mediterranean Religions Source Database

   Search:  
validated results only / all results

and or

Filtering options: (leave empty for all results)
By author:     
By work:        
By subject:
By additional keyword:       



Results for
Please note: the results are produced through a computerized process which may frequently lead to errors, both in incorrect tagging and in other issues. Please use with caution.
Due to load times, full text fetching is currently attempted for validated results only.
Full texts for Hebrew Bible and rabbinic texts is kindly supplied by Sefaria; for Greek and Latin texts, by Perseus Scaife, for the Quran, by Tanzil.net

For a list of book indices included, see here.


graph

graph

All subjects (including unvalidated):
subject book bibliographic info
aristocratic/egalitarian, choruses Seaford, Tragedy, Ritual and Money in Ancient Greece: Selected Essays (2018) 177, 181
egalitarian, as reflecting ideology, as reflecting purity rituals Ganzel and Holtz, Contextualizing Jewish Temples (2020) 77
egalitarian, ideology Raaflaub Ober and Wallace, Origins of Democracy in Ancient Greece (2007) 37
egalitarian, ideology, as reflecting Ganzel and Holtz, Contextualizing Jewish Temples (2020) 81
egalitarianism Balberg, Blood for Thought: The Reinvention of Sacrifice in Early Rabbinic Literature (2017) 116, 123, 151, 186, 197
Gabrielsen and Paganini, Private Associations in the Ancient Greek World: Regulations and the Creation of Group Identity (2021) 21, 62, 218, 219
Harrison, Brill's Companion to Roman Tragedy (2015) 153
Keith and Edmondson, Roman Literary Cultures: Domestic Politics, Revolutionary Poetics, Civic Spectacle (2016) 238, 239, 245
Raaflaub Ober and Wallace, Origins of Democracy in Ancient Greece (2007) 15, 32, 35, 37, 41, 43, 44, 45, 46, 51, 65, 77, 97, 120, 123, 167, 190, 191
Shemesh, Halakhah in the Making: The Development of Jewish Law from Qumran to the Rabbis (2009) 63, 64
egalitarianism, christians/ity Bremmer, Magic and Martyrs in Early Christianity: Collected Essays (2017) 26, 430
egalitarianism, godlikeness, and Bartninkas, Traditional and Cosmic Gods in Later Plato and the Early Academy (2023) 161

List of validated texts:
8 validated results for "egalitarianism"
1. Homer, Iliad, 2.243, 9.319 (8th cent. BCE - 7th cent. BCE)
 Tagged with subjects: • Aristotle on equality • Equality • egalitarianism • equality • law, equality before

 Found in books: Laks, Plato's Second Republic: An Essay on the Laws (2022) Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2022 210; Raaflaub Ober and Wallace, Origins of Democracy in Ancient Greece (2007) 27, 29, 120; Rothschold, Blanton and Calhoun, The History of Religions School Today: Essays on the New Testament and Related Ancient Mediterranean Texts (2014) 274

2.243 ὣς φάτο νεικείων Ἀγαμέμνονα ποιμένα λαῶν, 9.319 ἐν δὲ ἰῇ τιμῇ ἠμὲν κακὸς ἠδὲ καὶ ἐσθλός·
2.243 for he hath taken away, and keepeth his prize by his own arrogant act. of a surety there is naught of wrath in the heart of Achilles; nay, he heedeth not at all; else, son of Atreus, wouldest thou now work insolence for the last time. So spake Thersites, railing at Agamemnon, shepherd of the host. But quickly to his side came goodly Odysseus, "
9.319
Not me, I ween, shall Atreus son, Agamemnon, persuade, nor yet shall the other Danaans, seeing there were to be no thanks, it seemeth, for warring against the foeman ever without respite. Like portion hath he that abideth at home, and if one warreth his best, and in one honour are held both the coward and the brave;"
2. Aeschylus, Suppliant Women, 604, 607-608 (6th cent. BCE - 5th cent. BCE)
 Tagged with subjects: • equality • law, equality before

 Found in books: Liddel, Decrees of Fourth-Century Athens (403/2-322/1 BC): Volume 2, Political and Cultural Perspectives (2020) 207; Raaflaub Ober and Wallace, Origins of Democracy in Ancient Greece (2007) 112, 162

πανδημίᾳ γὰρ χερσὶ δεξιωνύμοις, ἔφριξεν αἰθὴρ τόνδε κραινόντων λόγον·, δήμου κρατοῦσα χεὶρ ὅπῃ πληθύνεται. Δαναός
NA>
3. Herodotus, Histories, 3.80, 5.78 (5th cent. BCE - 5th cent. BCE)
 Tagged with subjects: • egalitarianism • equality • gender, equality • law, equality before

 Found in books: Raaflaub Ober and Wallace, Origins of Democracy in Ancient Greece (2007) 97, 147, 158, 159, 162; Sharrock and Keith, Maternal Conceptions in Classical Literature and Philosophy (2020) 194; Wolfsdorf, Early Greek Ethics (2020) 510

3.80 After the tumult quieted down, and five days passed, the rebels against the Magi held a council on the whole state of affairs, at which sentiments were uttered which to some Greeks seem incredible, but there is no doubt that they were spoken. Otanes was for turning the government over to the Persian people: “It seems to me,” he said, “that there can no longer be a single sovereign over us, for that is not pleasant or good. You saw the insolence of Cambyses, how far it went, and you had your share of the insolence of the Magus. How can monarchy be a fit thing, when the ruler can do what he wants with impunity? Give this power to the best man on earth, and it would stir him to unaccustomed thoughts. Insolence is created in him by the good things to hand, while from birth envy is rooted in man. Acquiring the two he possesses complete evil; for being satiated he does many reckless things, some from insolence, some from envy. And yet an absolute ruler ought to be free of envy, having all good things; but he becomes the opposite of this towards his citizens; he envies the best who thrive and live, and is pleased by the worst of his fellows; and he is the best confidant of slander. of all men he is the most inconsistent; for if you admire him modestly he is angry that you do not give him excessive attention, but if one gives him excessive attention he is angry because one is a flatter. But I have yet worse to say of him than that; he upsets the ancestral ways and rapes women and kills indiscriminately. But the rule of the multitude has in the first place the loveliest name of all, equality, and does in the second place none of the things that a monarch does. It determines offices by lot, and holds power accountable, and conducts all deliberating publicly. Therefore I give my opinion that we make an end of monarchy and exalt the multitude, for all things are possible for the majority.”,
5.78
So the Athenians grew in power and proved, not in one respect only but in all, that equality is a good thing. Evidence for this is the fact that while they were under tyrannical rulers, the Athenians were no better in war than any of their neighbors, yet once they got rid of their tyrants, they were by far the best of all. This, then, shows that while they were oppressed, they were, as men working for a master, cowardly, but when they were freed, each one was eager to achieve for himself.
4. Plato, Laws, 757a, 757b (5th cent. BCE - 4th cent. BCE)
 Tagged with subjects: • equality • equality (geometrical) • equality, political (isonomia)

 Found in books: Ebrey and Kraut, The Cambridge Companion to Plato, 2nd ed (2022) 545; Omeara, Platonopolis: Platonic Political Philosophy in Late Antiquity (2005) 188; Petersen and van Kooten, Religio-Philosophical Discourses in the Mediterranean World: From Plato, through Jesus, to Late Antiquity (2017) 57

757a δοῦλοι γὰρ ἂν καὶ δεσπόται οὐκ ἄν ποτε γένοιντο φίλοι, οὐδὲ ἐν ἴσαις τιμαῖς διαγορευόμενοι φαῦλοι καὶ σπουδαῖοι—τοῖς γὰρ ἀνίσοις τὰ ἴσα ἄνισα γίγνοιτʼ ἄν, εἰ μὴ τυγχάνοι τοῦ μέτρου—διὰ γὰρ ἀμφότερα ταῦτα στάσεων αἱ πολιτεῖαι πληροῦνται. παλαιὸς γὰρ λόγος ἀληθὴς ὤν, ὡς ἰσότης φιλότητα ἀπεργάζεται, μάλα μὲν ὀρθῶς εἴρηται καὶ ἐμμελῶς· ἥτις δʼ ἐστί ποτε ἰσότης ἡ τοῦτο αὐτὸ δυναμένη, διὰ τὸ μὴ 757b σφόδρα σαφὴς εἶναι σφόδρα ἡμᾶς διαταράττει. δυοῖν γὰρ ἰσοτήτοιν οὔσαιν, ὁμωνύμοιν μέν, ἔργῳ δὲ εἰς πολλὰ σχεδὸν ἐναντίαιν, τὴν μὲν ἑτέραν εἰς τὰς τιμὰς πᾶσα πόλις ἱκανὴ παραγαγεῖν καὶ πᾶς νομοθέτης, τὴν μέτρῳ ἴσην καὶ σταθμῷ καὶ ἀριθμῷ, κλήρῳ ἀπευθύνων εἰς τὰς διανομὰς αὐτήν· τὴν δὲ ἀληθεστάτην καὶ ἀρίστην ἰσότητα οὐκέτι ῥᾴδιον παντὶ ἰδεῖν. Διὸς γὰρ δὴ κρίσις ἐστί, καὶ τοῖς ἀνθρώποις ἀεὶ σμικρὰ μὲν ἐπαρκεῖ, πᾶν δὲ ὅσον ἂν ἐπαρκέσῃ πόλεσιν ἢ,
757a be friends with masters, nor bad men with good, even when they occupy equal positions—for when equality is given to unequal things, the resultant will be unequal, unless due measure is applied; and it is because of these two conditions that political organizations are filled with feuds. There is an old and true saying that equality produces amity, which is right well and fitly spoken; but what the equality is which is capable of doing this is a very troublesome question, since it is very far from being clear.
757b
For there are two kinds of equality which, though identical in name, are often almost opposites in their practical results. The one of these any State or lawgiver is competent to apply in the assignment of honors,—namely, the equality determined by measure, weight and number,—by simply employing the lot to give even results in the distributions; but the truest and best form of equality is not an easy thing for everyone to discern. It is the judgment of Zeus, and men it never assists save in small measure, but in so far as it does assist either States or individuals,
5. Thucydides, The History of The Peloponnesian War, 2.37.3 (5th cent. BCE - 4th cent. BCE)
 Tagged with subjects: • autochthony, and equality • egalitarianism

 Found in books: Barbato, The Ideology of Democratic Athens: Institutions, Orators and the Mythical Past (2020) 99; Raaflaub Ober and Wallace, Origins of Democracy in Ancient Greece (2007) 191

2.37.3 ἀνεπαχθῶς δὲ τὰ ἴδια προσομιλοῦντες τὰ δημόσια διὰ δέος μάλιστα οὐ παρανομοῦμεν, τῶν τε αἰεὶ ἐν ἀρχῇ ὄντων ἀκροάσει καὶ τῶν νόμων, καὶ μάλιστα αὐτῶν ὅσοι τε ἐπ’ ὠφελίᾳ τῶν ἀδικουμένων κεῖνται καὶ ὅσοι ἄγραφοι ὄντες αἰσχύνην ὁμολογουμένην φέρουσιν.
2.37.3 But all this ease in our private relations does not make us lawless as citizens. Against this fear is our chief safeguard, teaching us to obey the magistrates and the laws, particularly such as regard the protection of the injured, whether they are actually on the statute book, or belong to that code which, although unwritten, yet cannot be broken without acknowledged disgrace.
6. Cicero, Republic, 1.42 (2nd cent. BCE - 1st cent. BCE)
 Tagged with subjects: • equality under the law • equality,

 Found in books: Atkins, The Cambridge Companion to Cicero's Philosophy (2021) 225; Gilbert, Graver and McConnell, Power and Persuasion in Cicero's Philosophy (2023) 132

1.42 Deinde aut uni tribuendum est aut delectis quibusdam aut suscipiendum est multitudini atque omnibus. Quare cum penes unum est omnium summa rerum, regem illum unum vocamus et regnum eius rei publicae statum. Cum autem est penes delectos, tum illa civitas optimatium arbitrio regi dicitur. Illa autem est civitas popularis (sic enim appellant), in qua in populo sunt omnia. Atque horum trium generum quodvis, si teneat illud vinclum, quod primum homines inter se rei publicae societate devinxit, non perfectum illud quidem neque mea sententia optimum est, sed tolerabile tamen, ut aliud alio possit esse praestantius. Nam vel rex aequus ac sapiens vel delecti ac principes cives vel ipse populus, quamquam id est minime probandum, tamen nullis interiectis iniquitatibus aut cupiditatibus posse videtur aliquo esse non incerto statu.
1.42 In the second place, this function must either be granted to one man, or to certain selected citizens, or must be assumed by the whole body of citizens And so when the supreme authority is in the hands of one man, we call him a king, and the form of this State a kingship. When selected citizens hold this power, we say that the State is ruled by an aristocracy. But a popular government (for so it is called) exists when all the power is in the hands of the people. And any one of these three forms of government (if only the bond which originally joined the citizens together in the partnership of the State holds fast), though not perfect or in my opinion the best, is tolerable, though one of them may be superior to another. For either a just and wise king, or a select number of leading citizens, or even the people itself, though this is the least commendable type, can nevertheless, as it seems, form a government that is not unstable, provided that no elements of injustice or greed are mingled with it.
7. Dead Sea Scrolls, Community Rule, 5.2, 6.13, 8.10 (2nd cent. BCE - 1st cent. CE)
 Tagged with subjects: • Ethnic boundary making model, equalization • egalitarianism

 Found in books: Shemesh, Halakhah in the Making: The Development of Jewish Law from Qumran to the Rabbis (2009) 63, 64; van Maaren, The Boundaries of Jewishness in the Southern Levant 200 BCE–132 CE (2022) 154, 155

NA>
8. Plutarch, Cimon, 8.1, 15.3 (1st cent. CE - 2nd cent. CE)
 Tagged with subjects: • equality • equality (in moral evaluation)

 Found in books: Chrysanthou, Plutarch's 'Parallel Lives': Narrative Technique and Moral Judgement (2018) 139, 141, 143; Raaflaub Ober and Wallace, Origins of Democracy in Ancient Greece (2007) 78, 145

8.1 ταῦτα καίπερ οὐδαμοῦ τὸ Κίμωνος ὄνομα δηλοῦντα τιμῆς ὑπερβολὴν ἔχειν ἐδόκει τοῖς τότε ἀνθρώποις. οὔτε γὰρ Θεμιστοκλῆς τοιούτου τινὸς οὔτε Μιλτιάδης ἔτυχεν, ἀλλὰ τούτῳ γε θαλλοῦ στέφανον αἰτοῦντι Σωφάνης ὁ Δεκελεὺς ἐκ μέσου τῆς ἐκκλησίας ἀναστὰς ἀντεῖπεν, οὐκ εὐγνώμονα μέν, ἀρέσασαν δὲ τῷ δήμῳ τότε φωνὴν ἀφείς· ὅταν γάρ, ἔφη, μόνος ἀγωνισάμενος, ὦ Μιλτιάδη, νικήσῃς τοὺς βαρβάρους, τότε καὶ τιμᾶσθαι μόνος ἀξίου. 15.3 ἐκεῖνά τε τὰ πρὸς τὴν ἀδελφὴν ἀνανεούμενοι καὶ Λακωνισμὸν ἐπικαλοῦντες. εἰς ἃ καὶ τὰ Εὐπόλιδος διατεθρύληται περὶ Κίμωνος, ὅτι
8.1 Although these inscriptions nowhere mentioned Cimon by name, his contemporaries held them to be a surpassing honour for him. Neither Themistocles nor Miltiades achieved any such, nay, when the latter asked for a crown of olive merely, Sophanes the Deceleian rose up in the midst of the assembly and protested. His speech was ungracious, but it pleased the people of that day. "When," said he, "thou hast fought out alone a victory over the Barbarians, then demand to be honoured alone.",
15.3
It was to these calumnies that the famous and popular verses of Eupolis about Cimon had reference:âx80x94 "He was not base, but fond of wine and full of sloth, And oft heldº sleep in Lacedaemon, far from home, And leave his Elpinicé sleeping all alone." But if, though full of sloth and given to tippling, he yet took so many cities and won so many victories, it is clear that had he been sober and mindful of his business, no Hellene either before or after him would have surpassed his exploits. 16



Please note: the results are produced through a computerized process which may frequently lead to errors, both in incorrect tagging and in other issues. Please use with caution.
Due to load times, full text fetching is currently attempted for validated results only.
Full texts for Hebrew Bible and rabbinic texts is kindly supplied by Sefaria; for Greek and Latin texts, by Perseus Scaife, for the Quran, by Tanzil.net

For a list of book indices included, see here.